1. What is Philosophy of Mind?
Martín Abreu Zavaleta
May 27, 2014
1 The questions
Humans have minds, but rocks, pencils and underwear don’t (perhaps luckily). At the same time, mentality
seems to come in different degrees of complexity. For instance, cats and dogs seem to have
minds, but their minds are presumably much less complex than our own: they can’t formulate
thoughts about mathematics, for instance, and for all we know, they are not capable of linguistic
understanding.
The main task of Philosophy of Mind is to give an account of the nature of the mental. We approach the
issue by asking certain kinds of interesting questions:
- What does it take for something to have mentality? That is, in what circumstances can we
attribute something mental properties like being in pain, believing or desiring something?
- What is it to be in a particular kind of mental state? For instance, what is it to be in pain, to
have a belief, or to perceive something?
- What is the relationship between the mental and the physical? Mental properties seem
radically different from physical properties, as some philosophers have emphasized. So how
can the physical and the mental interact? Moreover, some people think that there are only
physical things and properties, so that whatever mental properties are, they have to be
reducible to physical properties. But if mental and physical properties seem so different,
how could the reduction be possible in the first place? How can the mental interact with the
physical?
When we’re doing philosophy of mind, we’re not trying to tackle a question about the specific
mechanisms by which beliefs are generated, or the process from a beam of light striking your retina to
conscious awareness. Those are very important questions, but they are better addressed by science. Part of
what we are trying to find out is whether a scientific explanation of mentality can be given, and if so, how.
This may be initially hard to understand, but as you read more philosophy, you will come to understand the
kind of explanations that we’re after.
1.1 Mental phenomena
There are different kinds of mental phenomena. In this course we will focus on two:
-
Intentional states:
- Mental states that are about something. For instance: beliefs, desires,
knowledge, etc.
-
Phenomenal states:
- Mental phenomena that involve sensations, or a certain way it is like to have
them. For instance, if you look at a sunflower, there is a way it looks like to you: it looks
yellow, and this way of looking is part of your visual experience. When you bite a peach,
there is also a certain way it feels like: sweet, perhaps a bit sour, a certain kind of raw feeling.
2 Basic metaphysical notions
-
Substance:
- Some people may define a substance as something that can exist independently of other
things. For instance: chairs, tables, people, and particles are substances. Shadows, smiles,
laps, and hallucinations, are not substances. A quick, perhaps defeasible, test to see whether
something is a substance is this: if we can conceive of a possible situation in which only x
exists, then x is a substance; otherwise, x is not a substance.
For instance, we can conceive a situation in which only a chair existed, or one in which only
a particle existed, but we can’t conceive of a situation in which only a smile existed.
-
Properties:
- Properties are qualities that substances can have. For instance, my mom’s cat has the
property of being spotted, and right now you have the property of reading the lecture notes.
When we want to say that something has a given property, we often say that that thing
instantiates the property, or that it exemplifies the property. In general, we will use the variable
F for properties, as a way of talking about an arbitrary property.
Not only substances can have properties. For instance, philosophers often think that properties
themselves can have properties: for instance, the property of being red has the property of
being instantiated—this is so because there is at least one thing which is red. Properties
like redness, having a belief, experiencing pain, etc., are usually called first-order properties.
Properties of properties are usually called second order properties, but for now we can only
worry about the first order properties.
-
Relations:
- Presumably, you are in New York as you read these notes. That means that you stand in
a certain property with the city of New York. This is the relation of being in. You may stand in
this relation to other places, like Chicago, Boston, or Mexico City. You may stand in different
relations to different objects.
-
States, events, processes:
- Think of a computer. At the very least, it has two states: on and off. We
can see the passing from one state to another as an event. For instance, when you turn on your
computer, there is an event of your computer chaging from the state OFF to the state ON. We
can see a process as a series of states and events that are causally connected. For instance, the
process starting with your computer being OFF, its change of state and the final state ON is
a process. In most cases, the states, events and processes that we care about are much more
complex than this, but you get the idea.
-
Ontology:
- Ontology tries to answer the question what exists. There are two uses of the expression
‘Ontology’. One is as the study of what exists, or what there is. The other is as a special
commitment of a theory as to what exists. For instance, we say things like this “Contemporary
physics is committed to an ontology of particles”, or we say that physics has particles in its
ontology. What we mean is that if the sentences that constitute physical theory are true, then
particles must exist (roughly). In this course, we commit ourselves to an ontology including
substances, properties, states, events and processes, but which substances, properties, etc. in
particular we should be committed to is a matter of controversy. Hopefully, by the end of the
course you will have made up your mind as to what ontological commitments you want to
take on board when it comes to the nature of the mental.
-
Supervenience:
- A supervenes on B if and only if there can be no difference with respect to
A without a difference with respect to B. Equivalently: A supervenes on B just in case if
everything remains the same with respect to B, then it also remains the same with respect to
A.
Some philosophers think it’s a mistake to talk about minds as if they were substances. Instead, some of
these philosophers prefer to talk about mentality as a more general phenomenon. Something is said to
have mentality if it has at least some mental property—for instance, if it has some beliefs,
conscious experiences, or any other kind of mental state. Thus, for these people, having a mind is
not like having an iron pan or a punching bag. Rather, having a mind is more like having a
property.
3 Mind-Body Supervenience
When someone says that the mental supervenes on the physical, she might mean any of the
following:
-
Generic SV:
- Any two things that are exactly alike in all their physical properties must be exactly
alike in all their mental properties.
-
Strong SV:
- If anything x has a mental property M, there is a physical property P such that x has P,
and necessarily any object that has P has M.
-
Global SV:
- Any two worlds that are exactly alike in all physical respects are alike in all mental
respects as well.
For our purposes, the generic version will do.
3.1 Physicalism
Physicalists are usually described as thinking that all entities that exist are either things recognized by
fundamental Physics, or reducible to things that are so recognized. One way to understand the
relevant notion of reduction is by means of one of the supervenience thesis we presented above.
Physicalists want to claim that all the mental properties a given object may have are metaphysically
determined by the physical properties it has—though as we’ll see in a bit there are many possible
formulations of physicalism, and which one is the best and most satisfying formulation is a matter of
controversy.
At the very least, our generic formulation of supervenience is a claim that every physicalist is committed to.
Here are some more substantive formulations of physicalism, all of which accept some version of the
mind-body supervenience:
-
Substance Physicalism:
- The only kinds of substances that exist are physical substances. Any
substance is either a minimal such substance or an aggregate of some such substances.
-
Nonreductive physicalism (property dualism):
- Mental properties are distinct from and
irreducible to any physical properties.
-
Reductive physicalism:
- Psychological properties are either identical or reducible to physical
properties.
4 Looking for the mark of the mental
4.1 Epistemological criteria
-
Direct knowledge:
- Direct knowledge doesn’t rest on evidence. Kim also describes it as being a
sort of non-inferential knowledge (knowledge that doesn’t rely on an inference). For instance,
you don’t seem to infer your knowledge that you’re experiencing great pleasure as you bite a
juicy mango. Unfortunately, this doesn’t seem like a good candicenter for a mark of the mental,
since we seem to have direct knowledge of some physical facts. For instance, you seem to
know directly that there is a computer in front of you (or a piece of paper, if you’re reading
this from a hard copy).
-
Privileged access:
- If you are experiencing some sort of mental state, it’s tempting to say that only
you can know it the way that you do. You know it from the inside, so to speak. Others may
come to know that you are in that mental state if they examine your brain or something like
that, but only you can know it directly. Unfortunately, there are other things that we seem to
be able to know in a privileged way, but are not mental phenomena: for instance, the position
of our limbs.
-
Infallibility and Transparency:
- Infallibitlity: if you believe that you are in a certain mental state
M, then you are in mental state M. Transparency: if you have a certain mental state M, then
you are aware that you have such state. Can you think of any mental phenomena that are not
transparent or with respect to which we are not infallible?
4.2 Intentionality
People call intentionality the feature of being about something, or being directed. For instance, your belief
that the sun is shiny is about something: the sun. But we can also have mental states that are directed
towards things that don’t exist: some people wish to find their true love, or the fountain of youth. It makes
sense to desire those things, but it doesn’t make sense to kick, pull or eat something that doesn’t exist. What
do you think? Do all mental states exhibit intentionality?